The Limits of the Principle of Compositionality in Semantics

 The Limits of the Principle of Compositionality in Semantics


Semantics, the study of meaning in language, often relies on the principle of compositionality—the idea that the meaning of a sentence is determined by the meanings of its parts and how they are combined. While this principle helps explain the productivity of language, it also faces several important challenges. In this article, we’ll explore the main problems that arise when relying solely on compositionality to explain meaning.

1. Sentence Meaning vs. Speaker Meaning

Let’s start with a simple scenario:

- Speaker A: “I love you.”
- Speaker B: “What a wonderful day.”

Now, imagine a similar exchange:

- Speaker A: “I hate you.”
- Speaker B: “What a wonderful day.”

Although Speaker B’s sentence is identical in both cases, the meaning is not. The words “what,” “a,” “wonderful,” and “day” are the same, but the intended meaning changes depending on the context and the previous statement. This highlights a crucial distinction: Sentence meaning (the literal meaning derived from the words and their combination) is not always the same as speaker meaning (what the speaker intends to convey).

A robust theory of semantics must account for this difference.

2. The Problem of Contextualized Effects

Consider the sentence: “I am hungry.”

- If a middle-class person says this, it might simply mean, “Let’s have lunch.”
- If a beggar says it, it could mean, “I need some money.”

The literal meaning is the same, but the context changes the interpretation. The principle of compositionality cannot fully explain these contextualized effects. This is known as the problem of contextualized meaning.

3. The Knowledge Problem: Linguistic vs. World Knowledge

Take the sentence: “Please open the window.”

- The literal meaning is straightforward: someone wants the window opened.
- But in context, it might actually mean, “I feel hot.”

To understand the intended meaning, you need more than just linguistic knowledge—you need world knowledge (or encyclopedic knowledge) about how people behave and why someone might want a window opened. A robot or an alien, lacking this world knowledge, would miss the intended meaning.
Thus, compositionality leads us only to the literal meaning, not the full, intended meaning.

4. The Problem of Individual Differences

Let’s look at the sentence: “I like coffee.”

- For one person, “coffee” might mean a hot, black, bitter drink.
- For another, it could be creamy, cold, and sweet.

Similarly, “gold” might mean a shiny, yellow metal to most people, but to an expert, it could mean something much more specific, like its chemical properties.
Despite these individual differences, we still manage to understand each other. But if we can’t even agree on what “coffee” or “gold” means, how can compositionality alone explain how we communicate meaning?

Summary: The Challenges for Compositionality

To recap, the principle of compositionality is a powerful tool for explaining how we generate and understand new sentences. However, it faces several significant challenges:

1. Sentence meaning vs. speaker meaning
2. Contextualized effects
3. The need for world knowledge
4. Individual differences in word meaning

These problems show that while compositionality is essential, it is not sufficient on its own to explain all aspects of meaning in language. Future theories of semantics must address these challenges to provide a more complete understanding of how we communicate.


Reference:

SEMANTICS-4: Problems Facing the Principle of Compositionality. (n.d.). [Video]. YouTube. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VB1zJRJfeyI


Post a Comment

Previous Post Next Post